Three Rules for Tackling a World-Famous Math Problem

BLOG: Heidelberg Laureate Forum

Laureates of mathematics and computer science meet the next generation
Heidelberg Laureate Forum

 

While I was listening to Sir Andrew Wiles speak, I saw the writer next to me had jotted three adjectives on his pad: “Calm. Elegant. Precise.”

Astute as those three words are, they miss the basic strangeness of Wiles’ life story. For all his calm, elegance, and precision, the guy is also a unicorn, a sasquatch, a one-of-a-kind creature from the pages of myth. He is, if you will, a walking oxymoron.

He is a celebrity mathematician.

20160926070420_00005

When he proved Fermat’s Last Theorem in 1994, it captured the public imagination in a way that few mathematical breakthroughs ever have. Usually, great mathematicians earn fame in their professional circles, but can walk down streets unnoticed. Wiles was different. He became the subject of bestselling books and primetime documentaries. He became “Sir.”

The difference, of course, was the problem he solved. Fermat’s Last Theorem can be explained to a high school student, but actually proving it took three centuries. It’s like the old board game commercial says: “a minute to learn, a lifetime to master.”

Or in this case, five lifetimes. Maybe more, if Wiles hadn’t come along.

20161031143242_00011

Last autumn, Wiles spoke at the Heidelberg Laureate Forum in Germany—a conference putting young researchers in math and computer science into contact with living legends such as Wiles.

After describing the history of Fermat’s Last Theorem—and emphasizing its mathematical importance over the romantic tale of his work on it—Wiles answered their questions.

In the process, and without naming them as such, he articulated three clear and compelling rules for how—and whether—to tackle a famous problem.

20160926070420_00006

Famously, Wiles hid his work on Fermat’s Last Theorem. He labored alone in an attic office, and covered his silence by discreetly releasing a trickle of research he’d saved up.

But this wasn’t what Wiles originally planned.

“I didn’t actually embark on it in secret,” Wiles says. “I did tell at least one or two people at the beginning.”

Wiles soon regretted that confidence. “It’s like issuing a weather forecast on the BBC. They wanted an update every hour and a half.”

20161031143242_00012

That’s when Wiles went into intellectual hiding. “The secrecy was very much to give myself peace to work on it.”

For top researchers tackling famous problems, it’s the only way. “If you’re working on the Riemann hypothesis,” Wiles says of another famous problem, “there’s no point in telling people. They’ll just hound you.”

20160926070420_00007

At his talk, an audience member asked Wiles about how to get started on a similar problem—such as proving that there are infinitely many perfect numbers.

“To be perfectly honest,” Wiles said, “I would say, ‘Don’t do that one.’”

Wiles’ reasoning relied on a key word: responsibility.

“I worked on Fermat[‘s Last Theorem] as a child, because I just loved the problem,” Wiles said. “But when I became a professional mathematician, I thought it was irresponsible.”

Glorious old problems like these are seductive. Prove a famous conjecture, and you might score not only a publication in the Annals of Mathematics but a profile in the New York Times or a BBC documentary: Wiles-level fame.

But in that seduction lies the danger. You can waste years chasing the pot of gold, and wind up empty-handed.

20161031143242_00013

So why did Wiles return to Fermat’s Last Theorem as an adult? Because other researchers proved it was closely linked to a deep problem in algebraic number theory: the Taniyama-Shimura Conjecture.

“Then,” Wiles said, “I knew it was responsible to work on it. This was a problem that had to be solved, in the middle of mainstream mathematics, with lots of structure to it.”

That’s the other key word: structure. Deep connections to other ideas of value.

“Pick a problem that really appeals to you,” Wiles advises, “but pick one that has some structure—so even if you don’t succeed, you will prove other things.” Even if you never reach the pot of gold, you want to gather some coins along the way.

20161031143242_00014

Perfect numbers don’t fit the bill. “Don’t be irresponsible and pick something where after two thousand years, there’s still no more structure to it [than when it was first stated].”

20160926070420_00008

Finally, Wiles echoed the wisdom of a popular mathematical canard: Theorems are proved by believers.

“It’s a very odd thing in mathematics,” said Wiles, “that if you know something is true, it’s much easier to prove it.” There’s a mystery of human psychology here. “Having the choice between it being ‘true’ and ‘not true,’ you’d think, well, you spend half the time on each. But it doesn’t work that way.”

Researchers might try to prove a statement true for years—and then start looking for counterexamples, and find one quickly. Or they might spend ages searching for counterexamples—then, briefly supposing that it’s true, they’ll happen swiftly upon a proof.

Somehow it’s hard to entertain both thoughts at once.

Wiles, who has learned this lesson better than anyone, puts it succinctly: “You have to really believe.”

hlf16_tuesday©hlff-flemming_04.jpg

© Heidelberg Laureate Forum Foundation / Flemming­ – 2016

Avatar photo

Posted by

is a math teacher. He blogs at Math with Bad Drawings and is currently working on two books for the publisher Black Dog & Leventhal. His writing has appeared in The Atlantic, the Los Angeles Times, Slate, Business Insider, the Chicago Tribune, and the Huffington Post.

1 comment

  1. Andrew Wiles 3 rules sound interesting for everybody but have quite another meaning for mathematicians than for ordinary people. Who for example intertprets rule #2 (Don’t be selfish) the way Wiles does, namely “work in a field where there is structure”. But it makes sense for a mathematician, because the work of a mathematician is thinking and nothing else. A mathematician is therefore selfish, if his thoughts only solve his personal problems and do not contribute anything to the problems of contemporary mathematics. Pure thoughts can therefore be selfish – but only if you are a mathematician.

Leave a Reply


E-Mail-Benachrichtigung bei weiteren Kommentaren.
-- Auch möglich: Abo ohne Kommentar. +